Significance of Spinocian philosophy in the theory of embodied cognition
Keywords:
Philosophy in Spinoza, embodied cognition, cognitionAbstract
Introduction: In addressing the value of Spinoza's philosophy for understanding the theory of embodied cognition, we aim first of all to approach the premises from which the author as a thinking being of the 17th century starts. The essential characteristics of his philosophical system and his ethics contribute to explaining how the theory of embodied cognition is heir to his philoethical thought. Materials and methods: We have started from a systematic and in-depth epochal and bibliographical study, which includes readings of the classic work of Baruch Spinoza. In order to clarify the intentions of the work undertaken, we have analyzed various studies associated with social cognition, in particular the theory of embodied cognition that account for their connection. Results: The 17th century is a century of closed dimensions, of systems whose structure includes a multiplicity of different theoretical bodies presided over by gnoseology, logic or the ontology-ethics-anthropology unit. Concepts about society and humanity had as their starting point the investigation of the individual and the need to make the world rational, that is, to renew it and keep it eternally changed. From this perspective, science acquires a true meaning when it is placed at the service of man. Discussion:The century is defined as the century of metaphysics, establishing Newton's mechanics as an invisible wall. Philosophy assigns a universal social and technical value to all its doctrines, that is, all philosophical currents are valued as producers of an absolute and definitive system of unquestionable truths about reality. Conclusions: In this context, philosophical positions are absolute and extreme, because philosophers are rationalists or empiricists; and materialists or idealists. From the gnoseological theory, the century inherits the best of Renaissance thought from these absolute perspectives and develops the modern conception of the philosophical system.
References
Bainbridge Cohen, B. (1993/2012), Sensing, feeling, and action: The experiential anatomy of body-mind centering, Northampton: Contact Editions.
Casanova, C, (2016). Estética y producción en Karl Marx. Santiago: Metales Pesados.
Clark, A. y D. Chalmers (1998): “The extended Mind”, Analysis, 58 (1), pp.7-19.
Damasio, A. (1994). El error de Descartes, Madrid: Destino.
Debruille, J. B., M. B. Brodeur y C. F. Porras (2012). “N300 and social affordances: A study with a real person and a dummy as stimuli”, PLoS ONE, 7 (10), e47922.
Español, S. (2017). Si queremos saber cómo sopla el viento podemos mirar la arena. Pensar el desarrollo psicológico observando el movimiento. En La segunda persona y las emociones. Buenos Aires (Argentina): SADAF.
Fingerhut, J. (2014). “Extended Imagery, Extended Access, or Something Else? Pictures and the Extended Mind Hypothesis”, en: Marienberg y Trabant (eds.), Bildakt at the Warburg Institute, De Gruyter.
Gallagher S. (2008). “Direct perception in the intersubjective context”, Consciousness and Cognition, 17, pp. 535–543.
Gallagher S. (2015). “Reuse and body-formatted representations in simulation theory”, Cognitive Systems Research, doi, 10.1016/j.cogsys.2015.07.003
Gallagher, S. y S. Varga (2014). “Social constraints on the direct perception of emotions and intentions”, Topoi, 33 (1), pp. 185-199.
Gomila, A. (2002). “La perspectiva de la segunda persona de la atribución intencional”, Azafea, Vol. 4.
Gomila, A. (2008). “La dimension moral de la perspectiva de segunda persona”, en Pérez, D. y L. Fernández (eds.). Cuestiones Filosóficas: ensayos en honor de Eduardo Rabossi, Buenos Aires: Catálogos, pp. 155-173.
Husserl, E. (1989). Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology and to a Phenomenological Philosophy: Second Book, Studies in the Phenomenology of Constitution, trad. R. Rojcewicz y A. Schuwer, Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
Lindblom, J. (2015). Embodied Social Cognition, Heidelberg: Springer
Marx, K. (2010). Manuscritos de economía y filosofía. Madrid: Alianza.
Merleau-Ponty, M. (1964). Sense and Non-Sense, trad. H. Dreyfus y P. A. Dreyfus, Evanston: Northwestern University Press.
Merleau-Ponty, M. (1967). The Structure of Behavior, trad. A. Fischer, Boston: Beacon.
Merleau-Ponty, M. (1968). The Visible and the Invisible: Followed by Working Notes, trad. A. Lingis. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.
Merleau-Ponty, M. (2012). Phenomenology of Perception, trad. D. A. Landes, New York: Routldge.
Noë, A. (2004): Action in perception, MIT press.
O’Reagan, K. y A. Noë (2001). “A sensorimotor account of vision and visual consciousness”, Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 24, pp. 939-1031.
Rowlands, M. (2010). The New Science of the Mind, Cambridge: The MIT Press.
Sartori, L., C. Becchio y U. Castiello (2011). “Cues to intention: the role of movement information”, Cognition, 119, pp. 242-252.
Smith, L. B. (2013). “It’s all connected: Pathways in visual object recognition and early noun learning”, American Psychologist, 68(8), p. 618.
Soliman, T. y A. M. Glenberg (2014). “The embodiment of culture”, en: Shapiro, L. (ed.), The Routledge Handbook of Embodied Cognition, New York: Routledge, pp. 207-219.
Spinoza, B. (2009). Ética. Trad. Vidal Peña. Madrid: Alianza.
Stern, D, (2010). Forms of vitality. Exploring dynamic experience in psychology, the arts, psychotherapy and development, New York: Oxford University Press.
Varela, F. J., Thompson, E., & Rosch, E. (2017). The embodied mind, revised edition: Cognitive science and human experience. MIT press.
Published
How to Cite
Issue
Section
License
Copyright (c) 2025 Ivon Sosa Piedra

This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 International License.
This journal provides immediate open access to its content, based on the principle that offering the public free access to research helps a greater global exchange of knowledge. Each author is responsible for the content of each of their articles.